Chapter 2. History
of Political Thought
Plan
1. Chinese political thought.
2. Hindu political thought.
3. Greek political thought.
4. Roman political thought.
5. Islamic political thought.
§ 1. Chinese political thought
Despite the long dominance of a Confucian orthodoxy,
Chinese political thought rivals that of Europe
in richness and diversity. For purposes of periodization, it may be divided in
the following manner. During the Shang and Chou dynasties (c.1766 to 1122 BC,
and from 1122 BC) that ruled the lower Yellow River basin,
though there was as yet no political thought, a distinctive political tradition
developed. From the beginning of the disintegration of the Chou dynasty (after
770 BC) into a collection of warring states down to the unification of those
areas, which are still the core of ethnic China by the Ch'in dynasty (221 BC),
a great efflorescence of theorizing on government occurred.
This
was the 'hundred schools' period still referred to by contemporary Chinese as a
model of free and lively discourse (thus Mao's saying: 'let a hundred flowers
bloom, let a hundred schools of thought contend'). The most important of these
schools were Confucianism, Legalism, and Taoism. After the short-lived Ch'in
dynasty, China
was ruled by a succession of dynasties (from 206 BC) more or less committed to
Confucianism, though with some interludes in which Taoism and Buddhism for a
time captured the fashion at court. This period may be referred to as that of
official Confucianism, though this was a syncretic and evolving doctrine far
removed from the views of its founder. Undergoing a philosophical refoundation
during the eleventh and twelfth centuries (the neo-Confucian revival), Confucianism
remained the creed of the empire until the extinction of the last dynasty (in
1911), though its influence lives on in China as well as in the East Asian
cultural area.
The first texts in Chinese political thought were
long associated with the Chou dynasty, though subsequent scholarship has
established that some parts of them are later fabrications. These 'classics'
are compilations of poems, historical and court records, and writings on
divination, and it has been the traditional view that they incorporated the
written remains of a golden age of civilization. The most cryptic and elusive
sayings were invested with a heavy burden of meaning and generated lengthy
commentaries accordingly. Of particular significance are two political
traditions identified by these commentators. The first concerns 'the mandate of
heaven', being the notion that the ruling house is entrusted with the
governance of the empire provided its rule is virtuous and beneficent, but
forfeits the right to rule if the ruler becomes corrupt or disasters afflict
the population. The second concerns the exemplary moral behaviour of certain of
the early sage rulers, one of whom passed over his own son in order to select a
commoner of surpassing virtue to be his successor.
The first political thinker (leaving aside the
legalist Kuan Tzu, d. 645 BC, whose writings are notoriously corrupt) was Confucius
(K'ung Fu-tzu, 551-479 BC). Although the writing and transmission of other
texts was attributed to him in ancient times, his views may most reliably be
sought in the Analects. Later
traditions ascribed to him the status of a great official and even the
possession of supernatural powers, but it is clear from contemporary evidence
that he was a traveling scholar and teacher of very modest means who was never
greatly successful in catching the ear of the powerful despite holding minor
office for a period in his native state. Confucius's stated intention was to
revive the rites, ceremonies and usages of the languishing Chou dynasty, but
his proposals for dealing with the disorder and evil of his times contain
notable innovations. The Confucian ideal is rule by moral example rather than
by military supremacy or according to hereditary succession. The ruler should
so order his person and household that all men shall wish to be his subjects,
and no laws will be required to control their conduct. The advisers and
officers of the ruler's government should be men of genuine merit ('gentlemen')
as revealed by their learning and scholarly accomplishments. Confucius
believes that those adept at the scholarly arts will take 'benevolence' (the
chief Confucian virtue) as the standard for their conduct and will accordingly
work for the welfare of the common people whose labour is the only source of
real wealth. Confucius makes no distinction between familial and political
authority, regarding the society as an extension of the ruler's household and
the well-ordered family as the foundation of the state.
In carrying on many of the aristocratic traditions
and values of Chou civilization Confucius effected in them a considerable
transformation. He accepted without question the need for social hierarchy and
a division of labour (between peasantry and literati), but he thought most men
capable of some improvement through learning and did not himself withhold
instruction from those who presented even the meanest offering, provided they
showed application. He emphasized the many duties of the ruler to his subjects,
and of the men of learning to service for the state, and their obligation to
offer advice based upon their knowledge of the requirements of benevolence even
if this advice was unwelcome. And apart from
some references to a
(non-anthropomorphic) 'heaven' as the source of virtue and the arbiter of fate,
the underpinnings of Confucius's theory are secular rather than spiritual, the
correct observation of political rites and ceremonies being accorded something
of a religious dimension.
Confucians later developed this theory in strikingly
different ways. Mencius (Meng Tzu, r.372-289 BC), a scholar very influential in
his day, whose works came to be second in authority only to those of his master
in later times, chose to dwell on the Confucian view of the sources of virtue.
In a theory likened to western moral intuitionism Mencius held that the
'original heart' of each man (itself a reflection of the cosmic order) contained
the embryonic stirrings of the four virtues, the development of which depended
upon a favourable environment, and particularly an appropriate education. He
was sharply critical of the reliance upon force by the overlords of the time,
calling for kingly government in the interests of the people and going so far
as to justify tyrannicide. Hsun Tzu (c.298-238 BC), who was an official as well
as a teacher, advanced an opposed interpretation of the Confucian inheritance.
He saw appetite as the most salient aspect of human nature ('things few,
desires many'), though he also affirmed the universal human capacity for
learning and culture. Of a Hobbesian turn of mind (he was also insistent upon
the need for clear and consistent naming as the only foundation for proper
reasoning) and writing at a time of almost incessant warfare, he looked to the
civilization and its rites and ceremonies as the only source of order. Men must
learn virtue there from, the members of each generation requiring an arduous
schooling lest they remain mere creatures of appetite. For the oversight of
such a task a kingly government dominated by Confucian advisers was crucial.
Whereas Mencius was of a mystical turn of mind Hsun Tzu was a rationalist.
'Heaven' he reduced to the workings of nature, and declared that a nature was
indifferent to human strivings men were themselves the makers of their fate.
Legalism (or the 'school of method'), the chief
rival of Confucianism, did not stem from the writings of a single theorist, but
is rather an amalgam of diverse elements given a philosophical gloss by the
last great Legalist theorist, Han Fei Tzu (c.280-233 BC). The earliest
Legalists (setting aside Kuan Tzu, d. 645 BC) were ShangYang (d. 338 BC) and
Shen Pu-hai (c. 400-337 BC).
The former succeeded by his policies in raising the most westerly of the
warring states, Ch'in, to a pinnacle of efficiency and power, thus laying the
foundation for the unification of China under Ch'in aegis in the
following century. Shang Yang's intention was to organize the state as an
efficient instrument of war. Hereditary office holders were to be replaced by
able administrators who would take the will of the prince as law, and
agriculture and handicrafts were to be encouraged at the expense of merchant
activity and idle consumption. Contending doctrines were to be rooted out in
favour of the common people taking the magistrates as their teachers, and the
population was to be organized such that each group was responsible for the
conduct of its members. A contemporary of Shang Yang, Shen Pu-hai served for
some years as chancellor of the small state of Han. Although his writings now
exist only as fragments it is clear that he devoted much attention to
administrative technique and the methods of rule. His recommendations to the
ruler advise an approach to his duties, which has much in common with the
Taoist cultivation of non-attachment as the path to sagehood. The ruler is as
the hub of a wheel, unmoving while the ministers and officials, the spokes, are
in unceasing rotation. His will is crucial if government is to be possible yet
he remains the master of the situation by refraining from indicating his
preferences in advance of his decision and avoiding involvement in the framing
of actual policy.
These and other elements are drawn together in the
writings of Han Fei Tzu, along with Hsun Tzu perhaps the most rewarding of
Chinese political theorists for the western reader. Han Fei Tzu, having studied
under Hsun Tzu in his youth, takes over something of the latter's estimate of
human nature and its malleability though he severs it from the Confucian belief
in benevolence. He advances the view that the standards of the state will prevail,
as only these will produce order. In developing in a sophisticated and
philosophical manner the original Legalist notion that the state should be
organized such that the will of the prince should be the law, Han Fei Tzu
touches on a problem found much later in western thinking of this genre. The
administration of the state should be as ordered, as predictable, and as free
from personal caprice as possible - 'the law no more makes exceptions for men
of high station than the plumb line bends to accommodate a crooked place in the
wood' - thus establishing constraints which would also apply to the ruler.
The political theory of Taoism (not to be confused
with the religion of that name which developed later) is the most difficult to
elucidate. The earliest chapters of the writings attributed to Chuang Tzu
(written about the fourth century BC) advise the aspiring sage to withdraw from
the world. Man's strivings are all in vain in an indifferent universe; the wise
man therefore cultivates simplicity and uselessness and comes to comprehend
thereby the absurdity of human existence. In the writings ascribed to Lao Tzu
(which were written by about the middle of the third century BC) this advice
can also be found, as can a poetic and subtle elaboration of its metaphysical
basis. The too or 'way' (a term
used by the Confucians, but in a different sense) is all encompassing, and
being potentially without limit is beyond human comprehension. It is also 'unkind'
as its movement proceeds unchecked by and unconscious of the activity of man.
Accordingly the sage finds enlightenment in inaction. But in an argument
reminiscent of the advice of some Legalist writers to the ruler (and here it
should be noted that later commentators found a philosophical affinity between
Taoism and Legalism) Lao Tzu also maintains that it is precisely the Taoist
sage, with the calmness of mind that comes from a lack of attachment to the
transient things of the human world, who would make the ideal ruler. He then
elaborates a vision of rural simplicity in which the old practices are followed
and the clever are prevented from playing any role, inaction being also the supreme
political wisdom.
Apart from these three major schools others deserve
mention. Mo Tzu (c.479-390 BC), in his time a great rival of Confucius, was the
founder of a military order devoted to countering aggressive warfare. Arguing
that the Confucians in encouraging filial piety founded their political
philosophy upon partiality, which was the root cause of all conflict, he
developed a theory based on universal and equal regard (or love) for all men.
He was also critical of Confucius for wasting time and resources on elaborate
ceremonies and mourning rites, maintaining instead that every policy adopted by
the state should be directly addressed to the needs of the common people. How
he expected to identify and make effect such policies is not clear from his
extant writings. On the one hand he put forward a populist epistemology - what
is true can be seen, in part, from what the people believe - but, on the other,
he was also a strict advocate of the notion of identification with the
superior' to ensure that all in the state were obedient to a single direction.
Later followers of Mo Tzu, who constituted themselves into a quasi-religious
sect, developed a system of logic not inferior to that of the Greeks, but Mo
Tzu's influence thereafter declined and his writings were neglected until
recent times. China in this period was also host to the 'school of names', a
diverse collection of sophists and logicians who debated problems of existence,
relativity, causation and other such philosophical issues (Hui Shih, c.380-305
BC, stating Zeno's paradox of motion, and Kung-sun Lung writing at the same
time on the problem of particulars and universals). Although they did have some
impact on political thought, several of their number also holding political
office, their role cannot be compared to that of the Sophists of classical Greece. The
sophistication of Chinese writing on the politics and strategy of the warfare
that was endemic at the time should also be noted. The treatise traditionally
ascribed to Sun Tzu (perhaps to be identified with Sun Pin, who lived in the
fourth century BC, or his putative ancestor Sun Wu, of the preceding century),
apart from being a masterwork of strategy, explicitly develops the connection
between politics and war and contains a chapter on the techniques of subversion
worthy of the twentieth century. Finally, numerous metaphysical schools
(including the yin-yang, and
five element schools) flourished, though their impact on political thought was
not as yet direct.
When Ch'in unified ethnic China in 221 BC its rulers did so
under the banner of Legalism. The short and oppressive reign of the house of
Ch'in (the emperor advised by, among others, Li Ssu, fellow student with Han
Fei Tzu of Hsun Tzu) laid the foundation for the bad press Legalism has enjoyed
in China ever since, though in recent times Mao Zedong sought to improve the
reputation of the school by comparing the exploits of the Ch'in emperor with
his own achievements. When the Han dynasty (a name to become eponymous with the
Chinese people) chose to proclaim (in 141 BC) a single school as that to be
identified with the empire they chose Confucianism; but this was a Confucianism
transformed almost beyond recognition by the syncretic approach of the ' school's
proponents, and the practical exigencies of ruling a vast and populous domain.
The Han Confucians, of whom Tung Chung-shu (c. 179-104 BC) was the most
influential, tried to amalgamate Confucian political and moral philosophy with
the metaphysical and cosmological speculation of the yin-yang and five elements schools, and the exponents of the
divination notions found in the Book
of Changes (I Ching). Tung Chung-shu conceived of the universe as an
organic entity in which yin
(representative of all that is dark, submissive, female) yang (representative of ill that is
bright, aggressive, male) and derivatively the five elements (water, fire,
wood, metal, earth) are in constant movement according to a pre-determined
order. This movement produces the seasons, life, and man. Individual is both
the noblest of living beings and also a microcosm of the universe; his nature
(which is the source of the virtues, including benevolence) is admixed with
feeling or emotions just as in the universe yang intermingles with yin.
To develop his nature (for few can do this unaided) and thereby cause benevolence
to become manifest emotion regulated, man needs culture, which is the
responsibility of the kingly ruler to provide. Thus Tung Chung-shu has grafted
certain Confucian political and ethical notions upon an entirely different
metaphysics. His theory contains other elements, including a philosophy of
history in which dynasties succeed one another according both to the mandate of
heaven and also to a predetermined cycle of colours and cardinal positions; he
also advanced the view that portents and natural disasters were an indication
that the ruler had acted such that the correct order and pattern had been
violated, a transgression for which sacrifices and amends would be required.
Han Confucianism was also eclectic in its incorporation of many Legalist
practices in the administration of the empire. These were often openly acknowledged,
as in the 'Discourses on Salt and Iron' (81 BC) which is the record of a
dialogue between the Legalist-inclined defenders of the government's record
particularly on military and administrative spending, and their critics who
make consistent appeal to the Confucian value of frugality and the importance
to the state of ethical standards rather than the costly machinery of bureaucratic
compulsion. This lively and readable work is reminiscent of nothing so much as
a contemporary argument between socialists and free marketeers. Worthy of note
also in this period is the appearance of the first great Chinese history,
written by Ssu-ma Ch'ien (c. 145-90 BC).
For a time during the early centuries AD much
intellectual interest was focused upon Taoism, but thereafter Buddhism began to
exert a major attraction upon the Chinese intellect, reaching the height of its
philosophical, religious, and political influence during the T'ang dynasty (AD
618-906). It was to counter what some then saw as a foreign creed, as well as
to confront the philosophical issues (and particularly the problem of existence)
rose in Buddhist metaphysics, that a body of scholars began what has come to be
known as the neo-Confucian revival. Beginning in the Sung dynasty (960-1279)
the influence of neo-Confucianism spread, even despite the Mongol invasions, so
that by the beginning of the Ming dynasty (13 68-1644) it became the philosophical
orthodoxy. By this time the Chinese system of government rested upon the
regular selection of a bureaucracy through examinations in the Confucian arts
and writings, and the extensive use of printing had widely disseminated the
works of Confucius and his latter-day interpreters throughout the empire (and
to Korea, Japan and the private man and those of the state are at variance, and
that the ruler should exercise perfect liberty in the use of the 'two handles'
(rewards and punishments) to ensure that the standards of their students were
as much administrators and men of affairs as scholars, and their arguments
often had practical implications for government policy, and sometimes painful
consequences for themselves.
Although neo-Confucianism was a broad movement
embracing many varieties of argument, Chu Hsi (1130-1200) came to be acknowledged by the
fourteenth century as its leading exponent. The metaphysical foundation of Chu Hsi's political philosophy
resembles that of western neo-Platonism. Every existent thing is the material
instantiation of a particular and inflexible principle or standard: the
universe is therefore composed of that which is 'in shapes' or matter (ch'i), and that which is 'above
shapes' or principle (li). The
summation of all the principles in the universe is the Supreme Ultimate (t'ai chi), and as Chu Hsi's philosophy is
(following Han Confucianism) a philosophy of organism so the Supreme Ultimate
is immanent in each thing. The principle of a thing is, as in Platonism,
perfect, but in being clothed in material form the possibility of imperfection
and thus evil arises. In order to avoid evil and move towards the perfection
that is their unique principle, men (and particularly the scholar-literati)
must pursue mental cultivation, endeavouring to understand principles, and
thereby their summation, by 'the investigation of things'. Here Chu Hsi had in mind not so much
an empirical investigation of the material world as a leap of intuitive insight
akin to the 'sudden enlightenment' of Ch'an
(Zen) Buddhism, except of course that what was to be apprehended was the
pattern of an existent cosmic order rather than its fundamental unreality. New
force was given to the Confucian direction to 'rectify oneself and restore the
rites'. Having sought the Supreme Ultimate in himself the scholar had an
overriding duty to reform the human world according to the principles of which
he now had knowledge. Far from Confucianism being, as in Max Weber's view, a
comfortable and conformist creed, it imposed a heavy twofold burden or sense
of predicament upon its exponents.
Chu Hsi's ideas were sufficiently dominant to be described as
orthodoxy, but other scholars did develop contrary interpretations of the Confucian
tradition, most notably Wang Yang-ming (1472-1529) who maintained the identity
of the mind and the principle of things (li).
Thereafter Confucianism had its critics, and philological inquiry undermined
some of the traditional views as to the composition of the early texts, but it
remained a living force down to the end of the nineteenth century. The great
radical and moving spirit of the 1898 reform movement, K'angYu-wei (1858-1927),
based his policies (which if implemented would have destroyed much of the
traditional structure of the empire) on his interpretation of Confucius as a
reformer, and a thoroughgoing re-evaluation of Confucius was only initiated
during the intellectual ferment that accompanied the May Fourth Movement of
1919.
Modern Chinese political thought reflected the
influences of almost every variety of western political theory that found its
way into translation. The doctrine of nationalism, conforming in some respects
to the Chinese view of their identity, had many adherents, including Sun
Yat-sen (1866-1925). But even Chinese Marxism (see mao zedong) continued to incorporate many Confucian
preoccupations.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment